Pons Asinorum
By Joel Marks
Published in Philosophy Now, no. 35, p. 48, March/April 2002
Three travelers seek lodging for
the night. They come upon a pension that charges 10 euros per person. It turns
out that there is only one room available, but they don't mind sharing; so they
pay the clerk 30 euros. When the proprietor returns, however, she decides that
the guests should be given a discount for having to bunch up, so she summons
the bellhop and hands him 5 euros to refund to them. Not being a completely
honest fellow, the bellhop pockets two euros; this conveniently leaves one euro
to be returned to each guest. Therefore each guest has now paid nine euros, for
a total of 27 euros. But 27 plus the two in the bellhop's pocket = 29. What
happened to the thirtieth euro?
When I first heard
this puzzle, I was bedazzled. It seemed so simple; yet no matter how I turned
it over in my mind, I could not come up with a solution. I even entertained the
hypothesis that I must be dreaming, or under the influence of Descartes' evil
daemon, "who has directed his entire effort to misleading me, [for] how do
I know that I am not deceived every time I add two and three or count the sides
of a square or perform an even simpler operation, if such can be imagined?"
(Meditation One).
Soon, however, I
came up with this surprising conclusion: There is no thirtieth euro! The
travelers ended up paying 27 euros. The proprietor had 25, and the bellhop kept
two. THAT'S IT. And yet ... I still could not shake from my head the
notion that there was a missing euro. So it occurred to me that the puzzle
could be conceived as a kind of illusion -- a calculative illusion, we might
call it. An analogy can be drawn to a visual illusion, like the
bent-stick-in-water, which is not really bent, but, even when one is fully
knowledgeable of its straight shape, continues to APPEAR bent at the
waterline (due to the refraction of light). Just so, I now knew there was no
thirtieth euro, but I couldn't dispel the mental impression that there was.
Finally I was able
to dispel even the illusion. This came about precisely because of its
refractoriness. I could not rid my mind of that thirtieth euro; there had to be
a way to account for it. And so there is: For at the end, the proprietor has 25
euros, the bellhop two, and the guests three. VOILA: 30 euros! So NOW
the puzzle became: Why had there seemed to be a puzzle in the first place?
Indeed, for some of my more logically adept friends and colleagues, there had
been no puzzle about the 30th euro, and they were only puzzled about what was
puzzling me. I can still experience a kind of Gestalt switching (as when
viewing the picture of a vase and two facial profiles) between my puzzlement
and my lack thereof. What makes for the difference?
The answer I have
come up with is that this "puzzle" arises from a simple "mental
mishearing": Where the situation at the end is that the guests have PAID
27 euros, one might inattentively "hear" this as their now POSSESSING
27 euros. Then indeed there would be a mystery (for the bellhop only
possesses two, so where's the thirtieth?). But in fact at the end the guests
only retain three euros of the original 30.
I have therefore
passed through three stages: (1) puzzlement (indeed, astonishment), (2)
knowledge, but with remaining unease or residual illusion, and (3) "total
enlightenment" or "wisdom," with no puzzle or illusion extant
(and even understanding why there had been puzzlement in the first place). The
progression is instructive: From time to time life throws us for a loop, and,
indeed, PHILOSOPHY is in the very business of questioning fundamental
assumptions. But sometimes, as with the three lodgers puzzle, we eventually
discover a way to buttress our original conception of things; Wittgenstein
considered philosophy itself to be one big faux-puzzle maker, which it was his
calling to foil. However, the history of thought -- not to mention, the
narratives of our individual lives -- is surely rife with cases of a new
conception's replacing the old after some initial shock, such as the
discoveries of pi, the stellar nature of the Milky Way, the absence of an
ethereal medium, radioactivity, the expansion of the universe, the
incompleteness of arithmetic, and so many others. So the truly philosophical
task may be to discern which are the real and which the ersatz puzzles.
Which, for
example, is the Anthropic Cosmological Principle? It seems that the various
physical constants of our universe are exquisitely fine-tuned for the coming
into being of ... us! The odds of this having come about by chance are said to
be infinitesimal; ergo, we have empirical evidence of some (vast) intelligence
and purposiveness (God?) pre-existing the universe. Is this a genuine problem
for the secular mind?
Apparently NOT.
Here is a homely analogy. Suppose you hit a golf ball into the air and it comes
down in a dark forest. Well, no mystery there: Where it came down is where it
came down. If we want to explain why it landed where it did, we would naturally
look to physical laws and conditions. Now change the point of view: Pick a
particular point hidden in the deep woods and challenge somebody to strike that
precise location with the ball. We would expect only a Tiger Woods to attempt
the feat, but even he would probably find it impossible.
Just so, the
"fine-tuning" of nature that resulted in us may seem unlikely to the
point of impossibility (SANS an act of intentional design or creation),
but the refutation of this "mystery" is that we are just
"looking at things through the wrong end of the telescope": We pose
the "problem" from the vantage of the end‑point, whereas causality
works from the beginning, and then, whatever happens, happens. Thus, the
"problem" needs no solution because it is not really a problem.
Yet there are
others who see a deeper riddle posed by the constants of nature, and who
consequently disparage the formulation above as the "WEAK Anthropic
Principle," or "WAP." Is there a Strong Anthropic Principle
constituting a real puzzle? (Or would one just be a SAP to think so?) You will
have to consider that for yourself outside the confines of this column.
****************************************************************
Joel Marks is Professor Emeritus of
Philosophy at the University of New Haven in West Haven, Connecticut, U.S.A. He would like to thank Bill DeMayo and Julie
Chenell for prompting reflection on the present topics.
<< Home